The Value of Civilian Arms Possession As Deterrent To Crime Or Defense Against Crime
This article is copyrighted. It was provided by the author, Don B.
Kates, Jr., and is distributed with the permission of the author. It
can be uploaded to other BBSs as long as it is not altered, and it may
be cited as long as credit is given. As per Don Kates' note:
"If you publish this, you must indicate that it is the text
and footnotes to an article that appeared in v. 18 of the AMERICAN J.
OF CRIM. LAW (1991)." So noted.
The Value of Civilian Arms Possession As Deterrent To Crime Or Defense Against Crime
By Don B. Kates Jr.*
* LL. B. Yale University (1966). Member of the California,
District of Columbia, Missouri and United States Supreme Court Bars.
San Francisco partner, Benenson & Kates; of counsel, Hallisey &
Johnson, San Francisco, Ca. I wish to thank the following for
their assistance: Professors David Bordua (Sociology, U. of Illinois),
Philip J. Cook (Public Policy Studies and Economics, Duke U.), F. Smith
Fussner (History, Emeritus, Reed College), Gary Green (Criminology, U.
of Evansville),
Ted Robert Gurr (Political Science, U. of Colorado), John Kaplan
(Law Stanford U.), Raymond Kessler (Criminal Justice, Memphis State
U.), Gary Kleck (Criminology, Florida State U.), Daniel Polsby (Law,
Northwestern U.) James D. Wright (Social and Demographic Research
Institute, U. of Mass., Amherst); Ms. P. Kates and C. Montagu, San
Francisco, Ca. and Ms. S. Byrd and Mr. C. Spector, Berkeley, Ca. Of
course for errors either of fact or interpretation the responsibility
is mine alone.
Introduction
The crime reductive value of civilian firearms ownership is a
central issue in the "gun control" controversy. Sixty five years of
vitriolic debate have amply proven the wisdom of a leading early 20th
Century opponent of gun ownership, New York City Chief Magistrate
William McAdoo in predicting that
-
We shall make no progress in removing this national menace
until this basic fact as to the ineffectiveness of arming
citizens is well and thoroughly understood by the people who
foolishly buy pistols and arm themselves. [1]
The gun owner's almost talismanic faith in the protective efficacy
of guns leads him to cling to them notwithstanding the indubitable
evils to which guns all too often lend themselves. The other side seeks
to outlaw handguns (many would prefer outlawing all guns), dogmatically
convinced not just that, on balance, guns do more harm than good, but
that "In the hands of the general public handguns confer virtually no
social benefit" [2]; and, since legislatures have proved unwilling to
ban handguns, Magistrate McAdoo's intellectual descendants urge the
courts to do so, in effect, by imposing strict liability for the
manufacture, distribution or ownership of a gun. [2A]
Given the fervor of each side in this decades-old debate, it is
not surprising that neither has seemed fazed by the lack, until
comparatively recently, of any substantial quantum of hard evidence
upon which to base rational judgments about the supposed utility of
civilian firearms ownership in reducing crime. The purpose of this
paper is to analyze the empirical evidence on that issue most of which
has become available only in the last decade. [3] Prior to such
discussion it is necessary, however, to set out some caveats and two
definitions.
Caveats
Obviously the conclusions reached in this paper may have import
for the gun control debate; indeed in the case of at least one oft-
mentioned option they seem decisive. [3A] But this paper emphatically
does not attempt to resolve the general issue of the extent to which
public policy should circumscribe or allow gun ownership. To resolve
that would require broadly assessing at least the following: (1) not
just any crime reductive utility, but every other supposed benefit of
gun ownership to individuals or society generally (e.g. conservation
and ecology, promotion of national defense, deterring despotism etc.,
etc.); (2) comparison to those alleged benefits of all the costs (e.g.
accidents, violence and suicide) of gun ownership -- in light of a
hardheaded evaluation of (3) the likely extent to which non-compliance
or other factors might frustrate the salutory purposes of a gun ban,
(4) the costs to the criminal justice system of trying to overcome such
non-compliance, and (5) constitutional barriers either to particular
gun restrictions or to the means needed for their enforcement. [4]
In other words to determine what particular level of gun control
is desirable requires an enormously broader inquiry than is attempted
here. As the factors just enumerated suggest, it requires a pragmatic
inquiry: not just a balancing whether in the abstract of whether guns
do more harm than good but consideration of whether, in fact, any
particular control strategy will produce a favorable trade-off by
actually reducing the harms (or the more important ones) that involve
guns more than it reduces the values. [5] Such an inquiry requires
systematic attention to all the foregoing factors and to numerous
subsidiary issues, e.g. could the supposed benefits conferred by
civilian gun ownership be better achieved by non-lethal means? [6] In
contrast this paper is limited to only one sub-issue of #(1) of the
factors enumerated in the last paragraph.
My second caveat is that the disproportionate attention given
herein to studies and analyses authored by opponents of gun ownership
reflects necessity rather than a bias against gun ownership. The fact
is that the gun lobby has, in effect, defaulted as to the production of
academic literature. [6A] Thus studies by "gun control" advocates
constituted almost the whole corpus of academic literature available on
gun issues until the last decade when more neutral scholars began
addressing those issues. Significant of all too many aspects of the gun
control controversy is that gun owners require no scholarship -- nor
even "sagecraft" -- to maintain their talismanic faith in the
protective efficacy of guns, although they have produced a voluminous
technical literature on defensive weapons and tactics. [7]
Definitions
The first definitional problem was to find apt shorthand labels
for the respective positions of the gun lobby and its opponents. In
line with the imagery of religious faith this article employs, the
terms gun iconodule and gun iconoclast seemed appropriate. But the
difficulties inhering in terms of reference relating to a now-obscure
Byzantine religious controversy are obvious. So instead the terms "pro-
gun" and "anti-gun" will be used herein for the respective polar
extremes in the American gun controversy.
It bears emphasis that these "pro-gun" and "anti-gun" positions
are extremes -- albeit they have, tragically in my view, tended to
dominate and drown out more moderate voices. In fact, polls over the
past half century consistently show that most Americans, including a
majority of gun owners, are neither pro-gun nor anti-gun but rather
"pro-control". [7A] On the one hand, most Americans reject anti-gun
disdain for self-defense and the basic anti-gun creed of the inherent
depravity of guns. On the other hand, most Americans also reject the
puerile pro-gun shibboleth that the existence of laws against murder
and other violent crime makes it superfluous to reinforce them with
sensible, profilactic controls on weapons that can be used to commit
such crime. This article may be described as a self-conscious attempt
to apply the moderate pro-control position which characterizes the
rational majority to the claims which each extreme offers about the
crime reductive value of civilian gun ownership.
The second definitional problem involves distinguishing actual use
of a gun to thwart a crime in progress (hereinafter described as
defense-use) from the deterrent effect of actual or perceived victim
arms possession in dissuading criminals from attempting a crime at all
(hereinafter described as deterrence). Though basic, this distinction
has only rarely been observed even by criminologists and anti-gun
writers and almost never by pro-gun writers. It is crucial because
conceptual and practical difficulties make the evidence for deterrence
more complex and more ambiguous than for defense-use.
The order in which this article treats these issues is first
defense-use and then the possible deterrent effects of civilian gun
ownership. But before either aspect of defensive gun ownership can be
analyzed empirically certain ethical or cultural concerns must be
addressed -- if only because they have so often intruded into, and more
or less subtly obfuscated, purportedly empirical discussions of these
issues.
NON-EMPIRICAL (MORAL AND PHILISOPHICAL) CONSIDERATIONS
Some analysts see in the notoriously extreme bitterness of the gun
control debate a clash of cultural and ethical values disguised in more
or less pseudo-criminological terms. The proposition is not that
criminological disagreement is not a part of "the Great American Gun
War" but that such disagreement is minor in comparison to the violent
cultural and moral antagonism it cloaks. [8] Indicative of the depth of
those antagonisms is the description offered in the encyclopedic review
of American gun control literature done by the University of
Massachusetts for the National Institute of Justice): that many gun
control advocates seriously view gun owners as "demented and blood-
thirsty psychopaths whose concept of fun is to rain death on innocent
creatures, both human and otherwise" [8A]; that gun ownership is
"simply beastly behavior" the gun being both real and symbolic
mechanism of a peculiar savagery lurking in an American soul that is
"hard, isolate, stoic and a killer". [9] As one would expect, the pro-
gun is utterly different; as Col. Jeff Cooper, one of the more
articulate spokesmen for defense gun ownership, puts it:
-
Weapons compound man's power to achieve; they amplify the
capabilities of both the good man and the bad, and to exactly
the same degree, having no will of their own. Thus, we must
regard them as servants, not masters -- and good servants to
good men. Without them, man is diminished, and his
opportunities to fulfill his destiny are lessened. An unarmed
man can only flee from evil, and evil is not overcome by
fleeing from it. [10]
It might be argued that there can be no basis for rationally
evaluating these violently contradictory points of view, at least
insofar as they constitute professions of cultural, moral or quasi-
religious premises. But even fundamental premises are not necessarily
immune from rational evaluation. A doubtless apocryphal tale holds that
when James Joyce publicly repudiated his Catholicism he was approached
by an English reporter who asked him if he would now become a
Protestant. "Just because I've lost my faith", Joyce is said to have
replied, "do you think I've lost my reason as well?" The point is that
it is sometimes or to some extent possible to determine whether
professions of moral faith are founded in reason. Thus, for instance,
the anti-gun response to Cooper's profession of faith is: that a guns
is simply not an effective defense to criminal attack; that to flee if
possible, and otherwise to submit, constitutes the only viable form of
opposition to robbery, rape etc. [10A] Whether this is so will be
explored infra. But if it proves to be true, Col. Cooper's faith that
guns allow resistance to evil is exposed as contrary to reason.
Examination of Some Non-Empirical Elements of Anti-gun Faith-
Some professions of anti-gun morality may also be subject to
refutation either as contra-factual or as internally inconsistent: A
prime instance of internal inconsistency occurs in connection with
statements like those of the distinguished nationally syndicated
columnist and cultural historian Garry Wills who feels that "gun
fetishists" are at once immoral and unpatriotic, "traitors, enemies of
their own patria", "anti-citizens" arming "against their own
neighbors." [11] Yet what Prof. Wills and the many others who echo such
statements contemplate as the appropriate response when people are
subjected to criminal attack is summoning a police officer. [11-1]
There is an amusing, but none the less very real, impediment to
analyzing this position: it is so inconsistent that one who does not
start out accepting it is hard put to believe that Prof. Wills et al
are actually saying what they are, in fact, saying. Thus I emphasize
that their concern is not simply pragmatic, e.g. to deny that gun-armed
self-defense is effective or to laud the obvious advantages of police
assistance when that option is open. Entirely independent of (though
often accompanying) such pragmatic concerns, anti-gun advocates advance
the moral view that under no circumstances is it ever legitimate to use
a gun in defense of self or family. [11A] Thus Prof. Wills holds that
people who own guns in order to be able to protect their families in
the event that police assistance proves not immediately available
exhibit a morally abhorrent attitude toward fellow-Americans. [11A] Of
course, if consistently adhered to, Prof. Wills' view is as immune from
rational dispute as is any other moral belief. But if one is willing to
call on others (the police) to defend his family with a gun it is
patently inconsistent to condemn the morality of others because they
are willing to defend their families themselves if the police are
unavailable when the need arises.
Another common profession of the anti-gun faith is that which
characterizes defensive gun ownership as "paranoid". [12A] What
"paranoid" means in this context is not entirely clear (at least
today). It may now be no more than a psych-jargon dressed expression of
Prof. Wills' abhorrence of defensive gun ownership. But what "paranoid"
literally conveys is a view that was common among American
intellectuals up to about a decade ago. In that view the extent of
crime had been vastly exaggerated as a result of public hysteria; crime
was neither increasing nor dangerous or pervasive enough to justify
being armed; such a precaution so far exceeded the real level of danger
as to be an irrational overreaction. [12B] Thus it may be useful to
compare defensive gun ownership to another kind of precaution that is
generally deemed sensible. Homeowners who buy earthquake insurance are
considered not paranoid but prudent even in California where such
insurance runs at least $2.00 per $1,000.00 valuation, or $300.00
annually (for what is a middle class dwelling
at California prices, c. $150,000.00). [12C] Over a ten year period the
homeowner will pay $3,000.00 in earthquake insurance premiums. In
contrast, a used Smith & Wesson .38 special revolver, which will last
forever with proper maintenance, costs perhaps $150.00. Yet the
likelihood of an average American household (much less one in a high
crime area) suffering burglary or robbery over that period is roughly
10 times greater than of injury from all natural disasters (flood,
earthquake, hurricane, tornado) combined [13].
Can defensive gun ownership be deemed an irrational
overreation if it is reasonable to pay 20 times as much to insure
against a danger less than one tenth as likely? The gun owner might
even argue that his weapon is a better investment in that it may
actually avert the anticipated harm while insurance only recoups its
costs. It may be objected that insurance is not comparable to a gun
since insurance always pays off, but whether gun ownership protects
against crime is a matter of controversy. True enough, but beside the
point which is "paranoia". If the empirical evidence discussed infra
proves the gun owner's faith in the weapon's protective efficacy to be
wrong then wrong is what it is -- not "paranoid". That gun ownership
does not represent so exaggerated a perception of the crime problem as
to constitute irrational overreaction is made evident by the now well
accepted view that crime makes life significantly more dangerous here
than it is in many other countries. [13-1] Moreover, if fear of crime
equates to paranoia, the mental health of gun owners appears actually
to be superior to that of non-owners; apparently because gun owners
feel more confident about their ability to deal with crime, studies
find them less frightened of it than are non-gun owners living in the
same areas. [13A]
But whatever the benefits of lessened fear to gun owners, for
society in general what is unquestionably more important is the part
guns play -- some people believe it causative -- in about 33,000
suicides, accidents and murders annually. [14] Thus regardless of any
fear reductive effect, gun ownership may be contra-indicated,
particularly for people in the high-risk groups for gun abuse [15].
But, as noted earlier, the desirability of a univeral gun ban, or of
any other particular level of restriction, involves issues far beyond
the scope of this article.
The police as a source of personal protection for individual
citizens. Another possible interpretation of the paranoia
characterization is that defensive gun ownership is "paranoid" because
personal self defense has been rendered obsolete by the existence of a
professional police force. Regrettably this exaggerates the factual
effects of policing and totally misstates its function in law and
theory, as plaintiffs who attempt to sue for non-protection have found.
[16] Doubtless the deterrent effect of professional policing helps
assure that many will never be so unfortunate as to live in
circumstances in which they will require personal protection. But for
those who do need such protection -- e.g. women threatened by former
boyfriends or husbands -- the fact is that the police do not function
as bodyguards for individuals.
Rather the police function is to deter crime in general by patrol
activities and by apprehension after the crime has occured. If
circumstances permit, the police should and will protect a citizen in
distress. But they are not legally duty bound even to do that, nor to
provide any direct protection -- no matter how urgent a distress call
they may receive. [16] A fortiori the police have no responsibility to,
and do not, provide personal protection to citizens who have been
threatened (although in major cities police may perform bodyguard
services for the mayor and other prominent officials).
Typical of cases enunciating the non-responsibility of the
police for protecting individual citizens is Warren v District of
Columbia [17] in which three rape victims sued the city and its police
department under the following facts: Two of the victims were upstairs
when they heard the other being attacked by men who had broken in
downstairs. Half an hour having passed and their roommate's screams
having ceased, they assumed the police must have arrived in response to
their repeated phone calls. In fact their calls had somehow been lost
in the shuffle while the roommate was being beaten into silent
acquiesence. So when the roommates went downstairs to see to her, as
the court's opinion graphically describes it, "For the next fourteen
hours the women were held captive, raped, robbed, beaten, forced to
commit sexual acts upon each other, and made to submit to the sexual
demands" of their attackers. [19]
Having set out these facts, the court promptly exonerated the
District of Columbia and its police, as was clearly required by
-
[the] fundamental principle of American law that a government
and its agents are under no general duty to provide public
services, such as police protection, to any individual
citizen. [19]
As the phrase "fundamental principle of American law" suggests,
this holding is not some legal aberration unique to the District of
Columbia. It is universal, being enuciated by formal statute as well as
judicial decision in many states. [20] Nor is it simply a cynical ploy
for government to avoid just liability. The proposition that
individuals must be responsible for their own immediate safety, with
police providing only an auxiliary general deterrent, is inherent in a
high crime society. Consider the matter just in terms of the number of
New York City women who each year seek police help, reporting threats
by ex-husbands, ex-boyfriends etc.: to bodyguard just those women would
exhaust the resources of the nation's largest police department,
leaving no officers available for street patrol, traffic control, crime
detection and apprehension of perpetrators, responding to emergency
calls etc., etc. [21] Given what New York courts have called "the
crushing nature of the burden" [22], the police cannot be made
responsible for protecting the individual citizen. Providing such
protection is up to the individual who is threatened; it is not the
function of the police.
"Vigilantism" and related concepts
In tandem with anti-gun disdain for armed self-defense [22A] the
common misunderstanding that the police exist to protect individuals
has given rise to an elusive, but frequently expressed, attitude that
equates gun use in defense of self or others to "vigilantism". A
striking facet of this attitude is that it not only outweighs but even
reverses the approbation normally accorded Good Samaritans: Thus based
on a study of those who rescued crime victims and/or arrested their
attackers, PSYCHOLOGY TODAY disapprovingly characterizes them in terms
of the fact that 81% of these Good Samaritans "own guns and some carry
them in their cars. They are familiar with violence, feel competent to
handle it, and don't believe they will be hurt if they get involved."
[22B] Similarly an anti-gun survey actually classifies gun owners as
"violence prone" based on positive responses not to questions about
criminality but about the legitimacy of using force in order to stop a
crime in progress or rescue its helpless victim. [22C] Similarly the
editor of a book on the legal status of Good Samaritans introduces it
with the question
-
Are we to encourage the ordinary citizen to take direct
action in the prevention of crime or the apprehension of
criminals, after centuries of social development clearly
pointing toward the elimination of vigilante [sic] action and
the concentration of responsibility in the hands of public
officials? [22D]
Implicit in the foregoing quotation is as close to a definition as
such references to vigilantism ever seem to come: though Good
Samaritanism is highly creditable in other contexts, it somehow becomes
"vigilante action" if it involves "the ordinary citizen" in "the
prevention of crime or the apprehension of criminals...." (i.e.
defending self or others. As with Garry Wills' views, [22E] the
underlying concept seems to be that the defense of citizens is so
exclusively the job of the police that it is a usurpation for ordinary
citizens to defend themselves or each other. Thus in his critically
acclaimed book CRIME IN AMERICA former Attorney General Ramsey Clark
ringingly denounces gun ownership for self-defense on two (apparently
related) grounds: that it is atavistic and uncivilized, "anarchy, not
order under law -- a jungle where each relies on himself for survival";
and that it both usurps a state prerogative and ia a reproach to our
polity for gun owners arrogate to themselves the right to defend
themselves because: "A state in which a citizen needs a gun to protect
himself from crime has failed to perform its first purpose." [23]
For all its appeal to refined and high-minded (but uncritical)
readers, such an attitude lacks practicality in actual application. How
does society benefit if, instead of shooting the ex-husband who breaks
into her house, a woman allows herself to be killed because the
civilized thing to do is to wait for him to be arrested for her murder?
Far from advancing the cause of rational gun control, such attitudes
actually retard it by creating "straw men" which aid the gun lobby in
diverting attention from serious arguments for control. Unfortunately
such extreme anti-gun attitudes have played a part in shaping the
ideology and rhetoric of the gun control movement -- and have
particularly influenced its analyses of defensive gun use. Even
supposedly pragmatic works appear subtly colored by the unstated but
unshakable belief that, even when legal, defensive gun use represents
vigilantism or some other social wrong. It will suffice to present only
one example of this subtle coloration here since others will be
discussed infra:
As noted earlier, murderers generally have long prior histories of
criminal and otherwise dangerously aberrant behavior; domestic homicide
particularly
-
is often not an isolated occurence or outbreak, but rather is the
culminating event in a pattern of interpersonal abuse, hatred
and violence that stretches back well into the histories
of the parties involved. [24] The day-to-day reality is that
most family murders are prefaced by a long history of
assaults. [24A]
If the victims of homicidal attack are often related to or
acquainted with or their attackers, it follows that often times when a
victim has to kill in self defense the deceased attacker will have been
an acquaintance or relative rather than some unknown rapist, robber or
other intruder. Yet without so stating --or even mentioning the issue
at all -- anti-gun works invariably misclassify such lawful defensive
shootings as murder by lumping them together with real murder under the
misleading rubric acquaintance and domestic homicide. Viz. the almost
identical pseudo-statistical formulations in publications issued by the
Handgun Control Staff of the anti-gun U.S. Conference of Mayors to the
effect that "use of firearms for self-protection is more likely to lead
to ... death among family and friends than to the death of an
intruder." [25]
Even in a violent society the number of homicidally irrational
aberrants is so small that few of us have such friends, acquaintances
or relatives. But some people do have that misfortune. Of course it is
tragic when, for instance, an abused woman has to shoot to stop a
(current or former) boyfriend or husband from beating her to death. But
it is highly misleading to count such incidents as costs of gun
ownership by misclassifying them with the very thing they prevent:
murder between "family and friends". However atavistic or unpatriotic
such incidents may be, they are not vigilantism and they are not costs;
rather they are palpable benefits of defensive gun ownership from
society's and the victims' point of view if not from their attackers'.
Both Anglo-American and foreign law affirm what Prof. Wechsler
called "the universal judgment that there is no social interest in
preserving the lives of the aggressors at the cost of those of their
victims." [26] While medieval common law looked askance at the social
value of what it called homicide se defendendo, [27] later thinkers
from Grotius, Locke, Montesquieu, Beccaria and the Founding Fathers on
through Bishop, Pollock, Brandeis to Perkins and beyond have deemed
self defense unqualifiedly beneficial to society. [28] It is only the
unnecessary or excessive use of force that is harmful and wrong.
Furthermore, that harm is qualitatively the same whether the wrong is
commited by citizens or by the police. Unless "vigilantism" is a
solecism it must, on the one hand, not apply to lawful defensive use of
force by anyone, while on the other hand it must condemn all excessive
or unnecessary uses of force for the purpose of imposing summary
punishment, whether the vigilantes be citizens or police. [28A]
With the issue of vigilantism thus properly understood, concerns
over victim misuse of force can be seen in proper perspective. While
qualitatively the evil of vigilantism is the same whether committed by
civilians or police, quantitatively only police vigilantism is a major
social problem today. In contrast civilian vigilantism appears to be
quite rare -- perhaps because officials are alert to the need for vigor
in suppressing it. Civilians' claims to have used deadly force
defensively receive very close examination, with prosecution likely in
the event of wrongdoing. Unfortunately comparable review is rare when
police misuse of deadly force is suspected; several studies suggest
that a high proportion of police homicides are unjustified, [29] yet
officers are rarely prosecuted even for clearly wrongful use of deadly
force. [29A] These findings are buttressed by the extensive evidence
adduced in civil rights cases like Webster v City of Houston [30] in
which it was held to be a de facto municipal policy for each officer to
carry an untraceable "drop gun" to be planted on those he might shoot
(in order to falsely validate his later claim of self defense). It is
perhaps also significant that in comparing police to civilian shootings
of alleged criminals the police have been found to be 5.5 times more
likely to have shot an innocent person in the belief that he was a
criminal. [31]
This is not to deny that civilian gun misuse is a legitimate
subject of concern. The point is only that current legal sanctions
appear generally sufficient to deter civilian "vigilantism". So the
principal problem in this area is effective oversight of police use of
force. The American Civil Liberties Union's tergiversations about the
issue are significant: in 1968 the ACLU endorsed unspecified "gun
controls" on the express ground that this would safeguard dissenters
and the criminally accused from private violence. When the National
Coalition to Ban Handguns was organized, the ACLU gave specific content
to this position by joining. In the early 1980s the ACLU revised its
1968 resolution by deleting the express rationale, with membership in
the Coalition being continued without any express civil liberties
rationale. As of mid-1986, however, the ACLU has withdrawn from the
Coalition. In sum, however persuasive the general public policy reasons
for banning guns may be, they are not compelling as a civil liberties
issue. [32]
EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE AS TO THE VALUE OF ARMS, A pro-gun analysis
Earlier in this article the disproportionate attention it gives to
anti-gun analyses was attributed to their virtual monopoly of the
scholarly literature (until neutral criminologists began to discuss
defensive firearms use in the last decade). [33] Yet at least pseudo-
scientific analyses have sometimes appeared in material written for gun
owners and their sympathizers. One example is the apparently self-
published book MYTHS ABOUT GUNS by James E. Edwards whom the book's
rear jacket decribes as a lawyer and former mayor in Coral Gables, Fla.
In bold red letters the front jacket proclaims: "Theme of the book:
More Guns ... Less Crime". The jacket then proceeds to describe the
book's purpose as to provide
-
A concise, indexed, documented, pro-gun book of ready
reference which explodes the main dogmas and myths of the
anti-gun fanatics. Useful for debates, legislative hearings,
letters to the editor and fighting bad gun laws.
Mr. Edwards does energetically pursue that theme, offering three
tables and two graphs (albeit all reflecting the same data base) to
prove that "as shown by official studies firearms ownership and the
commission of crime ... gun ownership by the average citizen does not
promote crime but reduces crime." [33A] Each of these proofs compares
the percent of households in the East, South, Mid-West and West
respectively that in a single 1968 survey admitted owning either a
handgun or a gun of any kind to the rates of violent crime, property
crime and all crime respectively in those regions in the years 1968,
1972 and 1976. [33A]
Unfortunately such comparisons stumble on various methodological
obstacles, including: 1) radical changes in regional patterns of gun
ownership as indicated by mid-1970s survey data; [34] 2) that "survey
data on the level of national regions [results in] aggragated units too
large and internally heterogenous for useful analysis"; [35] and 3) the
sleight of hand Mr. Edwards uses to massage the data into suppporting
his argument. [36]
But above and beyond these problems is an even more basic
error which deserves extended discussion because of its almost
universal appearance when gun issues of any kind are analyzed by
partisans on either side. This lies in two assumptions whose fatuity
ought to be apparent to anyone who has ever had an introductory course
in social science. The first of these assumptions is that a correlation
between two phenomena is sufficient to prove that one of them has
caused the other. This may be illustrated by the fact that Mr. Edwards
is quite right about his "more guns ... less crime" correlation;
indeed, it is supported by far stronger evidence than he himself
presents. [37] But by the same token, there could probably be
established an equally strong negative correlation between more cows
... less crime. Before breaking into a paegn of praise to Bessie the
Great Protector, it might be wise to ask whether this correlation
represents anything beyond a spurious artifact of rurality: cows tend
to be found in rural areas and crime doesn't. Of course the low per
capita crime rates in rural America may be attributable to its high
rates of gun ownership. But for the rational and dispassionate observer
more proof of that is required than the bald correlation between "more
guns ... less crime."
Mr. Edwards' second false assumption is that, even where some
basis exists for deducing causation from a correlation between two
factors, which is the cause and which the effect can not be blithely
presumed according to one's preconceived perspective. This may be
illustrated by another frequently encountered, but erroneous, pro-gun
argument: that states which severely restrict handgun ownership have
higher crime rates than less restrictive states. [38] A factual
difficulty with this as a proof that gun ownership reduces crime is
that the studies do not consistently show the more restrictive areas
have more crime; some studies show them with no more crime than less
gun restrictive areas. [39] But even if the more restrictive were to be
found to have more crime, other explanations are equally or more
plausible than the deterrent or self- defense effects of gun ownership
in reducing crime. Prof. Polsby, refering to such a finding by a
respected scholar who is markedly less convinced of the value of gun
ownership than Mr. Edwards (or Prof. Polsby himself), notes [39A]:
Thus to evaluate the defensive utility of firearms it is necessary
to consider forms of evidence more directly relevant than mere
inference from comparisons of the crime statistics of different
jurisdictions or regions. This requires turning from pro- to anti-gun
authors since they provided the earliest attempts to analyze more
directly relevant forms of evidence. Because the latters' views will be
found even less persuasive under close scrutiny than than those of the
gun lobby it is important to reemphasize the definitions with which
this article began: the term anti-gun is not here used as a synonym for
"pro-control", but in its literal sense of antagonism toward gun
ownership. Such morally or culturally based antagonism (and an
associated disdain for the right of self-defense) underlies much of the
argument for banning handguns based on the purportedly empirical claim
that guns are useless for self-defense. But it simply does not follow
from the untenability of those claims that we must accede to puerile
gun lobby arguments against the need for rational control. The fact
that handguns are useful no more exempts them from reasonable
regulation than the fact that automobiles and innumerable other
commodities are useful preccludes reasonable regulation to minimize the
likelihood of their being misused. [39B]
Lawful self defense homicides as an index to defensive gun use -
The standard arguments against the utility of defensive gun
ownership date back to the early part of the Century; even their more
modern formulations were all written at least a decade ago. Because
directly relevant empirical evidence has been largely unavailable until
recently, such arguments have tended to be speculative rather than
empirical. For example it was (and is) argued that resistance is
useless and dangerous because criminals are more ruthless or better
shots or will have the drop on victims. [40] Where empirical evidence
has been cited it consists in idiosyncratic local statistics of self
defense homicide suggesting that gun use in self defense is a very
uncommon phenomenon. [41] From this it is argued that reduced gun
availability would confer great benefit at little corresponding cost
because "Guns purchased for protection are rarely used for that
purpose." [42]
Anti-gun argumentation from lawful homicide figures provides
clearly better evidence of the extent of defensive gun use than Mr.
Edwards', and other pro-gun attempts to infer it from differentials in
crime rates. But lawful homicide figures as an index to overall
defensive gun uses raise problems not only conceptually [43] but, more
important, factually. In the vast majority of defensive gun uses the
outcome is not that criminals die but only: that they are wounded or
injured or that they are apprehended or scared off without being
injured at all. [44] So even had far more broadly based long term,
geographically diverse lawful homicide figures been available before
the 1980s, homicides are too small a proportion of overall defensive
gun uses to be a reliable index to the frequency of such uses. At least
if better indexes were available, one would certainly not measure the
value of guns in police work by simply totting up the number of violent
felons police kill. By the same token lawful defensive homicides are
not a fair measure of the overall value of defense guns to civilians.
The justification for anti-gun use of the idiosyncratic local
justifiable homicide statistics is that until recently those have been
the only available data from which the extent of civilian defensive gun
use could even remotely be inferred. But this still does not excuse the
misleading selection and manipulation of such data. For instance, it is
well known (the point having been made often in anti-gun studies [45])
that householders rarely have the opportunity to use guns against
burglars since burglars take care to strike when no one is home to
shoot them. It was therefore misleading to cite as evidence that
defense guns are rarely used under any circumstances the rarity of
intruders being killed by householders. Concommitantly misleading was
the citation of such statistics without even mentioning [46] the much
higher incidence of lawful defense homicides of other kinds -- e.g.
woman kills homicidal ex-boyfriend, shopkeeper kills robber etc. [46A]
By the same token it was highly misleading to cite "guesstimates" by
Detroit, Los Angeles and New York City police officers of the number of
criminals civilians were killing there in the mid-1960s without
mentioning the availability from the Chicago Police Department of
complete and official figure showing that for decades the numbers of
lawful defensive homicides by civilians had generally equalled the
numbers by police and lately were tending to outnumber them by as much
as 3-1. [47]
The effect of these and other statistical manipulations was to
artificially minimize the incidence of lawful defensive homicides (and
therefore of overall defensive gun use inferrable therefrom) in the
anti-gun studies. Consider the now-discredited -- though still widely
cited -- comparison that handgun accidents kill 6 times as many
householders as householders kill burglars [48]. Based on this finding
of an anti-gun study of Cleveland gun deaths, it might be thought that
gun accidents must account for a substantial part of the yearly handgun
death toll; yet even nationwide the National Safety Council can
identify only about 300 accidental handgun fatalities annually -- as
compared to c. 6,000 handgun suicides and 6,000-9,500 handgun murders.
[49] The actual ratio of fatal handgun accidents to lawful defensive
killings is not six to one in favor of the former but more like 1 to 3
in favor of the latter. [50] While something unique about Cleveland
might explain this 1800% deviation from the norm, a more plausible
suggestion that has been made is that the number of accidents in
Cleveland was inflated by the random inclusion through
misclassification of large numbers of what were actually handgun
suicides. [51] In sum, the anti-gun attempts to minimize the extent of
defensive gun use could not have been sustained by full and accurate
description of even the sparse city-level lawful homicide data
available when the various anti-gun studies were written. [54]
Subsequently as such data have become available for other cities,
and on state and national bases, the anti-gun argument has suffered
further. [55] Though it does not publish them in its yearly Uniform
Crime Reports, the FBI now collects national "justifiable homicide"
figures which show armed citizens annually lawfully kill more violent
felons than do the police. [55] Yet even these figures actually
underrepresent the full extent of lawful defensive homicide by 50% or
more. The FBI statistics count as criminal any intentional killing
whose legality was initially questioned (even those later ruled lawful
by the district attorney, coroner's jury etc.). [56] Also, based on the
obsolete distinction between "excusable" and "justifiable" homicide,
the FBI excludes from the latter category any killing that occured in
defense of the defender's life rather than in repelling a felony having
some other object. In other words, however strange it may seem: if a
woman shoots an ex-boyfriend who is strangling her, or a contract
killer hired by her husband who wants to inherit her estate, the FBI
counts that as a criminal homicide (for statistical purposes only)
because the attacker's immediate purpose was only to kill her; but if
a merchant kills a robber or a woman kills a rapist the FBI counts that
as a justifiable homicide because the attacker's purpose was some crime
other than homicide. [56A] It is estimated that if all lawful civilian
self defense killings were counted, the actual number of violent
criminals killed by citizens might exceed the number killed by police
each year by as much as five times. [57]
Survey data as an index to defensive gun use
Until fairly recently survey evidence on gun issues was limited to
the results of whatever general unfocussed inquiries the Gallup or
Harris polls had haphazardly decided to ask in the 4 or 5 question
polls they had devoted to gun matters over the years. But during the
past decade both pro- and anti-gun groups have sponsored intensive
sophisticated multi-question private national surveys on various issues
in the gun control debate. Common to several of these private surveys
were questions as to whether guns in the respondents' homes had been
used defensively. The surveys were not conducted directly by the
partisan groups sponsoring them but by independent private polls
including Peter Hart and Patrick Caddell (for the anti-gun groups) and
the Decision Making Information organization (for the NRA).[57A]
Although less well known than Gallup or Harris, these are respected
polls: the Hart and Caddell firms regularly poll for Democratic Party
groups and candidates (President Carter and Senator Cranston among
them), while the Republican luminaries DMI has worked for include
Presidents Ford and Reagan.
As with any poll, these are subject to the objection that they
generalize about a population of upwards of 250 million on the basis of
information obtained from a sample of only about 1,500 supposedly
representative people. [58] But, excepting objections to surveys in
general, there is no reason for discounting the results of these gun
polls in particular; while these polls were paid for by partisans, the
reputations of the independent organizations actually conducting them
precludes any question of falsification and academic studies have
favorably cited and relied upon their results. [59] To exclude even
unreasonable doubts as to validity, however, the discussion here will
be based only on the evidence of anti-gun-sponsored polling. It is
possible to simply discard the results of the NRA-sponsored polls since
the data yields on defensive gun use from all the surveys are mutually
consistent. [60] Based only on the survey evidence sponsored by anti-
gun groups, it has been calculated that handguns are used in defending
against c. 645,000 crimes per year. [61] The magnitude of this figure
may be assessed by noting that it slightly exceeds the estimated number
of crimes committed or attempted by handgun-armed felons each year, c.
581,500. [62]
Thus the empirical evidence fails to sustain the claim that
handguns are often used in crime but rarely to defeat it. Since that
claim is the foundation of the legal theory for judicial abolition of
handgun manufacture via the doctrine of strict liability the fact that
defense uses approximate or actually exceed criminal uses might seem to
apply the coup de grace to that legal theory. But factual refutation
seems superfluous since the courts have not in any event found that
theory a legally sound basis for intruding into what they deem purely
legislative or political matters. [63] Yet the fact that defense uses
approximate or exceed criminal misuses emphatically does not refute the
need for legislatively imposed gun control. Controls carefully tailored
to disarm felons but not good citizens would reduce the incidence of
gun misuse but not of lawful defensive use. [63A] Moreover even a
complete ban might still be advocated on the theory that the possible
benefit of reducing suicide or homicide outweighs the certain cost of
reducing the overall number of crimes thwarted by defensive firearms
use. [64]
Two other problems with the comparison given above should be
noted: First, it is impossible to tell how much the c. 645,000 crimes
that handguns defend against overlap with the c. 581,000 criminal
attempts by handgun-armed felons. Doubtless in some cases handgun-armed
felon meets handgun-armed defender; but many cases involve either felon
or defender confronting an opponent who is unarmed or armed with a
knife, club, longgun or miscellaneous other weapon. [65] Next, it is
important to understand that the comparison is not of success in either
case but only of 581,000 handgun crimes attempted annually versus the
645,000 defense uses. Evidence from two sources suggests that handgun-
armed defenders succeed in repelling criminals (however armed) in 83-4%
of the cases. [70] But comparable evidence is lacking as to the rate at
which handgun-armed criminals succeed in crimes they attempt. [71]
As to the incidence of defensive gun use, an independent body of
data confirms the survey evidence of its frequency. This second data
source consists in formal or informal surveys taken among inmates of
various federal and state prisons over the past two decades. Some of
these surveys are methodologically crude and/or involve inadequate
samples. [72] But since the results of all of these surveys too are
mutually consistent and supportive, it will suffice to refer to the
latest and most recent which was conducted under the auspisces of the
National Institute of Justice in state prisons across the country. [73]
While most of its questions on victim arms possession focussed on the
question of deterrent effect (see discussion infra), several did
address self defense. Responding thereto, 34% of the convicts
-
said they had been "scared off, shot at, wounded or captured
by an armed victim," [quoting the actual question asked] and
about two-thirds (69%) had at least one acquaintance who had
had this experience. [73]
Also suggestive of the frequency of defensive gun use were
responses on two other points: 34% of the felons said that in
contemplating a crime they either "often" or "regularly" worried that
they "Might get shot at by the victim"; and 57% agreed that "Most
criminals are more worried about meeting an armed victim than they are
about running into the police." [74]
Peace of Mind
To continue the religious simile with which this article began,
one benefit which must (however reluctantly) be conceded by even the
most ardent atheist is that faith may be conducive to at least a
delusive peace of mind. Likewise anti-gun claims that "those who own
handguns for self-defense are engaging in dangerous self-deception"
[75] implies (however reluctantly) that at least delusive peace of mind
may be a benefit of the opposing faith. In fairness, even ardent anti-
gun advocates ought to admit the value of this in a society so crime-
ridden that they themselves proclaim that crime and the fear it creates
palpably diminishes the quality of life. [75] More neutral observers
forthrightly acknowledge that
-
If people feel safer because they own a gun and in turn lead
happier lives because they feel safer and more secure, then
their guns make a direct and nontrivial contribution to their
overall quality of life. [76]
Although increased peace of mind due to gun ownership may be
dismissed as a benefit only to the owners themselves and not to
society as a whole it may have wider ramifications. Two fear-related
problems that have received increasing attention in recent years are
the reluctance of by-standers either to come to the aid of victims or
to bear witness against their attackers. There has been no study of any
relationship that may (or may not) exist between witnesses' or victims'
gun ownership and their likelihood of cooperating with law enforcement
authorities. But studies have linked gun ownership to Good
Samaritanship: gun owners are apparently more likely than non-owners
both to feel a duty to come to the aid of others in distress and to
actually do so. [77]
Of course defensive gun ownership is a dangerous self-deception if
it causes gun owners to be injured or killed through involvement in
otherwise avoidable situations. But the evidence reviewed in the next
section does not suggest that gun ownership produces feelings of
invulnerability that encourage owners to recklessly court danger. If
anything, non-owners appear less able to evaluate the danger and the
opportunities of opposing criminals, and thus more inclined to unwise
opposition, than are gun owners.
POTENTIAL COSTS OF ARMED CITIZEN RESISTANCE TO CRIME
The "success" of defensive handgun use cannot be evaluated
independently of the most obvious and immediate problem of any kind of
resistance: that victims may suffer (additional) physical injury or
death who otherwise would only have been feloniously assaulted, maimed,
raped or robbed. Because of the paucity of evidence until very
recently, anti-gun arguments emphasizing these dangers have, once
again, generally had to proceed from speculation or anecdotal evidence.
[78] This lack of empirical evidence for the anti-gun viewpoint has
been obscured by a controversy which only superficially seems relevant
to the dangers of gun-armed self-defense -- largely because most of
the disputants are morally or otherwise opposed to gun ownership.
Based on national crime victim survey data, a number of scholars
who happen to be anti-gun recommend that victims eschew forcible
resistance of any kind; if an attacker cannot be "talked out" of his
crime, the victim should submit in order to avoid injury. [78A]
Doubtless this submission position would excite paroxysms of scorn from
defense gun advocates like Col. Cooper [78B]. But, in fact, its
scholarly critics have not been pro-gun nor have they urged gun-armed
resistance specifically. [78C] Their criticisms involve issues of
policy (that to advise victims to submit may encourage crime [79]) and
of methodological error (e.g. that, since the data do not show time
sequence, it is not clear how often victims are injured after they
resisted; they may have been harmed prior to any resistance in that the
criminal began the attack by gratuitously injuring them which was what
prompted them to resist). The latest, and probably the definitive,
analysis concludes that the "data, when interpreted carefully, do not
support any strong [general] assertions concerning the victim's safest
course of action when confronted by a robber." [80]
One criticism which has curiously been overlooked is that the
submission position is a parochial reflection of its expositors' own
sexual, racial and economic circumstances. In general, the submission
position literature has avoided any discussion of rape and invariably
it treats robbery and assault as the once-in-a-lifetime dangers which
they are (at most) for salaried white academics. It does not seem to
have even occured to any submission exponent to question whether the
calculus of costs and benefits of resisting might be different for
-
an elderly Chicano whom the San Francisco Examiner reports
has held onto his grocery by outshooting fifteen armed
robbers [while] nearby stores have closed because thugs have
either bankrupted them or have casually executed their
unresisting proprietors...
[Or] welfare recipients whom robbers target, knowing when
their checks come and where they cash them [or] the elderly
trapped in deteriorating neighborhoods (like the Manhattan
couple who in 1976 hanged themselves in despair over
repeatedly losing their pension checks and furnishings to
robbers).[80A]
Regrettably, for most victims crime is not the isolated
happenstance it is for white male academics. [81] Imagine the situation
of a Black shopkeeper, a retired Marine master sergeant who has
invested the life savings from "20-years-and out" in the only store he
can afford. Not coincidentally, it is located in an area where robbery
insurance is prohibitively high or unobtainable at any price. In
deciding whether to submit to robbery or resist, he and others who live
or work in such areas must weigh a factor which finds no place in the
submission position literature: that to survive they may have to
establish a reputation for not being easily victimized. [82] The
submission position literature is equally oblivious to the special
factors that may have importance for rape victims; even one rape --
much less several -- may cause catastrophic psychological injury that
may be worsened by submission, avoided by successful resistance and
mitigated even by unsuccesful resistance. [83]
By no means am I arguing that forcible resistance with guns (or
without) is optimum for crime victims in any or all circumstances. I am
only only laying out additional factors that really ought to be
considered before a well-salaried white, male intellectual presumes (as
I certainly would not) to tell the kind of people who are most often
crime victims what is best for them. [83A]
At the same time it must be recognized that the considerations
that underly the submission position are irrelevant to the defensive
value of guns, notwithstanding the coincidence that that position has
been championed largely by those who happen to be anti-gun advocates.
The evidence they cite does not focus on guns nor do lessons drawn from
less effective weapons seem to apply to resistance with guns. The only
extant study specific to gun-armed civilian resisters found they
suffered slightly lower rates of death or injury at the hands of
criminals (17.8%) than did police (21%). [84] These results are open to
question because the study involved only a very small sample. But
confirming evidence from an enormously larger data base is available in
the national crime victim surveys. (These, however, provide information
only as to victim injury, not death, since victims who died resisting
robbers are not available to answer survey questions.)
In fact, earlier versions of the national victim surveys were
cited by the one specifically anti-gun presentation which has tried to
empirically validate the dangers of resistance theme. [85] But the
survey questions in those early versions of the surveys lumped all
resistance together without differentiating the injury and success
rates of gun-armed resisters from those of resisters who were unarmed
or armed only with less effective weapons. The more recent national
victim surveys which do so differentiate have already been cited as
showing that victims who resisted with guns were much less likely to
lose their possessions to robbers than those who resisted with any
other kind of weapon. [86] As the Table below shows, this recent data
finds gun-armed resisters c. 50% less likely to be injured as victims
who did not resist at all. [87] In contrast, knife-armed resisters were
more likely to suffer injury than non-resisters and much more likely to
be injured than gun armed resisters; comparisons to other forms of
resistance are also favorable to the effectiveness of gun armed self-
defense. [87]
INSERT TABLE ABOUT HERE
Care must be taken to avoid exaggerating the importance of these
findings as support for the utility of defensive gun use. Ironically,
a major factor which might lead to exaggerating their import is a basic
conceptual error in anti-gun analyses of the utility of gun armed self-
defense. Implicit in many such anti-gun analyses has been the
unexamined -- indeed unstated -- assumption that having a gun somehow
compels the victim to resist with it even in circumstances that make it
senseless and dangerous to do so. [87-1] But the whole point of a gun
(or any other precaution against emergency) is to provide an option for
use if, but only if, this is wise under the circumstances.
With this point in mind it becomes evident that the survey data on
victim injury do not support any suggestion that victims who have guns
can safely resist no matter what the circumstances. On the contrary,
though guns do maximize successful resistance, of at least equal
importance in minimizing injury is that gun owners seem mostly to
eschew resistance when submission is the wiser choice. Although the
number of victims in the surveys who say they resisted with a gun is
not statistically insignificant, it is dwarfed by the number who tried
to flee or scream or resisted forcibly without a gun. [87-2] The much
higher rates of injury among victims who resisted in such ways do not
at all prove that resistance with a gun would have been safer in their
particular circumstances. Rather, the much smaller number of gun armed
victims who resisted at all suggests that gun owners may be
disproportionately less likely to resist when the circumstances for
that are inauspicious. Possibly gun owners are more likely than other
victims to have considered the dangers attendant upon resisting a
criminal and are therefore more hesitant to do so.
However absurd the concept of a thoughtful gun owner will seem to
Messrs. Grizzard, Braucher, Ellison, Wills, Clark, etc., [87A] analogy
may be found in the mid-1970s debate over the advisability of having
patrol officers wear bullet proof vests under their uniforms. Some
observers feared this might actually increase officer risk by producing
a sense of invulnerability that would lead officers to throw caution to
the winds. The actual result has been the reverse: wearing the vest
seems to remind officers of how vulnerable they really are, thereby
inclining them to increased caution. [87B] By the same token, when
civilians take the momentous step of buying and actually keeping a gun
for self-protection it may provoke them to a more sober consideration
of the risks of incautious resistance. The low rate of injury to gun
armed crime victims suggests they may be more capable of evaluating the
opportunities and risks of resistance than a non-owner who, having
never seriously contemplated the matter, is suddenly confronted by a
robber.
The risks and opportunities involved in the option to resist
gun ownership confers may be illustrated by considering some
alternative circumstances involving woman menaced by a rapist in her
home: if she becomes aware of him as he breaks in, the gun allows her
to frighten him off or capture and hold him for police [88]; but if her
first knowledge is being awakened by the pressure of a weapon against
her throat, nothing compels her to reach for a gun. Properly secreted
it remains available for use if, for instance, believing her cowed the
rapist becomes distracted in disrobing or by a police or fire siren or
some other external event [88A]; or if it becomes clear that he intends
to mutilate or kill her regardless, so that it is rational to resist no
matter how slim her chances of success. [89] In short, a gun simply
offers victims an option -- a dangerous option to be used only with
discretion and/or because throwing oneself on the mercy of a violent
attacker may be more dangerous yet. Fortunately people who have the
foresight to equip themselves with what for most victims is the only
effective means of resistance seem also to have the good judgment not
to try to use it when that would only serve to endanger them.
A Note on self defense and the Issue of Massacres In July,
1984 an unemployed and apparently deranged security guard killed 21
customers and employees at a San Ysidro California MacDonalds Hamburger
outlet. [90] In August, 1986 a similar massacre in which 15 died was
perpetrated in an Oklahoma Post Office by a recently discharged postal
worker using guns he had received as a National Guard marskmanship
instructor. [91] Both of the perpetrators remained on the scene to be
killed, eschewing any opportunity to escape before the police arrived.
It is ironic that these and similar tragedies of the past three
decades have been seen as arguing for, rather than against, gun bans.
[92] Massacre presents a situation in which the value of defensive
firearm use is at least arguable, while standard anti-gun arguments
have no force at all: The most important argument against forcible
resistance is that it may cause a criminal to kill a victim whom he
would otherwise only rob or rape. Obviously that argument has no
application to a situation in which a deranged killer opens fire
without provocation or making any demand for his victims to satisfy.
Also inapplicable by its own terms is the argument that even though a
gun ban may disarm the victim it may also disarm the attacker. Basic to
that argument is the proposition that in acquaintance or domestic
homicide situations killers often act out of momentary rage, not out of
a fixed intent to kill. From this premise it follows that such killings
might not occur but for the immediate access to firearms. [93]
Realistic gun control advocates recognize the impossibility of
disarming the killer who really wants to kill and wants a gun for that
purpose. They thus implicitly, and often explicitly, concede that gun
control measures can be of little use against killers so highly
motivated for personal or political reasons as to undertake massacres
which are substantially likely to result in their own deaths. [94] A
contrasting policy alternative for dealing with this
special problem is exemplified by an incident which occured in a
Jerusalem cafe four months before the San Ysidro MacDonalds massacre:
three terrorists who attempted to machine-gun the crowd were able to
kill only 1 victim before being shot down by handgun-armed Israelis.
When presented to the press the next day the surviving terrorist
bitterly complained that his group had not realized that Isreali
civilians were armed. The terrorists had planned to machine-gun a
succession of crowd spots, believing that they would be able to escape
before the police or army could arrive to deal with them. [95]
In sum, anti-gun policies not only offer no solution for the
massacre situation but are detrimental in precluding whatever chance
the victims might have to protect themselves in the crucial time it
will take the police to arrive on the scene. [96] Because terrorism is
its most pressing criminal justice problem, Israel maximizes the
presence of armed citizens by firearms training and encouraging gun
ownership and carrying by almost the entire populace (Jews of both
sexes and for the Druze and other pro-Israeli Arabs). [97] The
advisability of such measures in a country in which military training
is not universal even for males presents quite a different question -
which does not necessarily merit even examination since American
homicide is not primarily a matter of massacres. [97A] Melodramatic as
they were, the MacDonalds and Post Office massacres combined
constituted only a fraction of 1% of the criminal homicide totals for
those years. The massacre issue is thus a "red herring"; and the use
made of it by anti-gun advocates is at once ironic and evidence of the
simple-minded and/or unscrupulous debate which is, unfortunately, no
less characteristic of them than of the gun lobby. [98]
DETERRENCE
To reiterate, as used herein deterrence refers not to the actual
use of a gun in repelling an attempted crime (defense use) but to the
phenomenon of crime not even being attempted because of the potential
criminal's fear of confronting an armed civilian. There are several
kinds of such deterrence as Prof. Gary Green has noted in emphasizing
the need to distinguish between them: in "displacement" the effect when
some victims (or neighborhoods or communities) are perceived as well
armed is only the redirection of the same crime against others; in
sharp contrast are both "total deterrence", in which criminals are
deterred from crime altogether, and "confrontation deterrence", in
which they are deterred altogether from crimes like rape or robbery
which involve confronting a victim. [99]
Ignoring the vital distinction between displacement and total or
confrontation deterrence has allowed pro-gun advocates to present the
evidence on deterrence as less ambiguous and equivocal than it really
is. Blythely assuming that deterring crimes against victims perceived
to be well armed reduces the total quantum of crime -- rather than just
foisting it off on other victims -- extreme pro-gun advocates support
arming the populace as a deterrent to crime. Thus when Ford
Administration Attorney General Edward H. Levi proposed forbidding guns
in high crime areas, Ronald Reagan (then a private citizen) commented
in an article published in a gun journal:
-
Mightn't it be better in those areas of high crime to arm the
homeowner and the shopkeeper, teach him how to use his
weapons and put the word out to the underworld that it is no
longer totally safe to rob and murder?...
One wonders indeed if the rising crime rate isn't due as much
as anything to the criminal's instinctive knowledge that the
average victim no longer has any means of self-protection...
No one knows how many crimes are committed because the
criminal knows he has a soft touch. No one knows how many
stores have been let alone because the criminals knew it
[sic] was guarded by a man with a gun or manned by a
proprietor who knew how to use a gun. [100]
Local "experiments" in deterrence through publicizing gun ownership--
As pro-gun advocates like former NRA chief lobbyist Neal Knox are
quick to note, experiments involving the deterrent effect of an armed
victim population seem to have been very successful: [101]
-
in 1966 there were a series of brutal rapes in Orlando,
Florida which panicked the women of the city into buying
firearms for defense. Fearing a rash of accidental
shootings, the local news- paper co-sponsored a firearms
training class conducted by the police department; in the
next few months some 6,000 [sic -- the actual number was c.
3,000] women were trained in firearms safety and through the
extensively publicized program. The results were
remarkable... [In 1967] Orlando was the only city in the U.S.
of more than 100,000 population to show a decrease in crime.
Mr. Knox's article continues:
-
An equally startling example of the crime-deterrent value of
well-publicized gun ownership occured in 1967 in Highland
Park, Michigan, a Detroit suburb. Having read of the Orlando
and similar firearms training programs, Police Chief Bill
Stephens conducted a firearms training program for retail
merchants who were being plagued by an unprecedented number
of armed robberies... [This was denounced by the anti-gun
Detroit Police Commissioner] resulting in headlines in
Detroit newspapers. Four months after the program began
[Chief Stephens reported] that armed robbery of retail stores
had been averaging two every three days immediately prior to
the announcement of the training program; but from the day
the newspapers carried the story, there had been not a single
retail store robbery in the city -- for a third of a year!
-
[In Detroit itself a grocers' association sponsored such
classes which were publicized both because of the Police
Commissioner's criticism and because] in the following few
months seven armed robbers were killed by store owners -- and
Detroit grocery store robberies dropped by almost 90%. [103]
In fairness, pro-gun advocates have some excuse for missing
this point since their opponents have generally, though
unintentionally, diverted attention from it. Anti-gun works like HOW
WELL DOES THE HANDGUN PROTECT YOU AND YOUR FAMILY [105A] invariably
frame the issue as whether gun ownership actually protects the
individual family. By focussing on that pro-gun advocates have been
able to overlook the inconvenient reality that, though it clearly does
serve the interest of the individual gun owning family to displace
criminal attackers onto the unarmed, no larger social utility accrues
if such attacks are not thereby decreased overall.
Indeed, if displacement were the only effect it could be argued
that deterrence is actually socially deleterious. Assume for the sake
of discussion that programs that dramatize that women in a particular
area are well armed only displace rape to some other area where it is
less likely that the rapist will confront an armed victim. Of course
those who appraise probabilities more realistically than the gun lobby
will conclude that many times even armed victims will not be able to
defeat a criminal. [106] But from the perspective of overall social
benefit the important point is that the likelihood of rape being
repelled is enormously greater if the victim is armed than if she is a
helpless victim -- a fortiori even more so the chances that the rapist
will be apprehended or killed (thereby disabling him from further rape)
or frightened into eschewing rape in the future. [107] So deterrence
would be socially counter-productive if all it caused were
displacement, thereby actually diminishing the defense-use benefits
that would otherrwise accrue to society from civilian gun ownership.
Fortunately the deterrent effect of civilian arms possession is
not limited to displacement. As Prof. Green recognizes, realistically
the great majority of rapists are not, when deterred from striking at
one place, going to commit at least as many rapes elsewhere. Even as to
rapists who pre-plan their crimes, the reduction in incidence will be
not insubstantial since planning for a new area (i.e., out of the area
with which the criminal is most familiar) creates both real and
psychological problems. [108] Of course the incidence of rapes (or
other crimes) committed opportunistically may especially be reduced
when a criminal becomes frightened of the victims likely to be found in
his regular haunts.
At the same time it must be recognized that displacment effects
are not unique to the deterrent value of civilian gun possession; they
apply, and must be taken into account in appriasing, any kind of crime
deterrence program. For instance, a drastic increase in numbers of
uniformed police assigned to ride the New York subways at night was
followed by robbery reduction during those hours -- but robbery then
increased during daytime subway operations. Nevertheless since the
daytime increase was far less than the nighttime decrease the program
must be accounted a net success. [109] Thus the possibility of
displacement does not refute the value of programs designed to deter
crime, including publicizing victim armament. The point is only that
careful study, with displacement being taken into consideration,
is what is needed if the existence and extent of such net gain is to be
accurately appraised.
On the importance of deterring confrontation criminals into non-confrontation crimes
As suggested above, even as to rape it may reasonably be assumed
the deterrent effect of a highly publicized firearms training program
for potential victims may produce significant net reduction overall. As
to other kinds of crimes the deterrent effect may be much greater. The
difference is that because for rape there is no non-confrontation
alternative, the deterrent on a rapist must be total. In contrast, to
reduce the incidence of a crime like robbery the deterrent need only
frighten robbers into non-confrontation alternatives such as dealing
drugs, stealing cars, burglarizing unoccupied premises, forgery etc.
Since these are also serious felonies, such deterrence is not an
unalloyed benefit as Prof. Green has pointed out. [109A] But since
deterring confrontation crime into non-confrontation crime radically
decreases likelihood of victim death or injury, its social benefit is
very great.
This point has unaccountably been missed by those who have made
the one anti-gun argument that remains viable in light of present
evidence about the defensive value of arms possession. A leit motif
thoughout their analyses has been that guns are rarely used against
burglars because burglars take care to strike only when premises are
unoccupied. [110] It appears that a major reason for that care is fear
of meeting an armed householder. [111] If so, civilian arms
possession palpably and substantially benefits burglary victims by
minimizing their risk of injury or death in confrontations with
burglars. It is only because few burglaries occur when premises are
occupied that physical injury to victims is comparatively rare in
burglary. Victim surveys show injury to be quite frequent in the 12.7%
of burglaries that involve occupied premises. [112] The deterrent
effect of civilian arms possession can be largely credited for the far
lower rate of victim injury or death in burglaries than in robberies
which are, by definition, confrontation offenses. [113]
Thus programs that promote civilian arms possession palpably serve
the public good if the publicity they generate deters robbers into non-
confrontational burglary. It is worth noting that such non-
confrontantion deterrence constitutes a reversal of Prof. Green's
observation that displacement deterrence benefits only gun owners and
not society. In this instance civilian arms possession aids society but
not gun owners in particular for rarely do burglars know the gun
owners' homes from those of non-owners (nor, if the burglar is really
careful to strike when no one is home to shoot, would the distinction
matter to him). So any reduction in victim injury or death consequent
upon this care benefits potential victims in general but not gun owners
more than others. [114]
Difficulties and complexities of deterrent effects Though the
evidence so far reviewed provides relatively strong support for the
deterrent effect of civilian arms possession in the abstract, as to
formulating concrete policy it raises almost as many questions as it
resolves. Dramatic decreases in confrontation crime have followed in
the wake of local programs dramatizing victim arms possession. [114A]
But even leaving aside the issue of displacement, two questions suggest
themselves: would such programs be legal and practicable if tried on a
regional, state or anything beyond the purely local level; and, even if
such programs did work in broader application, does their deterrent
effect continue over time or is it merely transitory? [115]
Related to, but transcending, these questions is the probative
significance of such programs for the broader deterrent implications of
an armed civilian population. The gun lobby cites the apparently
dramatic effects of the Orlando and other local programs as proving
that widespread gun ownership must reduce violent crime. Now at least
unless one is a priori opposed to guns it will be intuitively evident
that to grow up in an area where criminals are frequently shot by
victims would at least tend to disincline people to confrontation
offenses. But this intuition is only remotely supported by such local
program results as the 90% reduction in Detroit grocery robberies when
gun training for grocers led to the well publicized shootings of 7
armed robbers. [116] Perhaps hearing of 7 such deaths over a few weeks
time has a shock effect on a fellow-robber that far exceeds the general
deterrent effect of having heard of 25-30 such deaths over the entire
period in which he grew up. Conversely, perhaps such a shock effect is
only temporary; perhaps having grown up hearing of two or three such
deaths each year would produce a greater deterrent effect on the
prospective criminal's psyche over the long run. But
"perhapses" are not evidence; or, rather, they are evidence of the
numerous questions that remain after such evidence as exists is
evaluated.
Moreover in evaluating these and other questions it must be
remembered that a deterrent does not constitute an absolute bar to
crime but only a disincentive, something which counters tendencies and
creates disinclination. In an area where opportunities for non-
confrontation crime are low, the incentive to rob might well outweigh
the aversive tendency or disinclination created even for criminals who
have grown up routinely hearing of incidents of robbers being killed by
their victims. Doubtless widely publicized firearms training for
victims (or a series of shootings of criminals by victims) might
dramatically reduce the number of robberies for some period of time.
But perhaps this result would reflect only an immediate shock effect
without lasting impact on robbery rates.
Nor can the evidence as to burglary be heedlessly generalized to
suggest that civilian arms possession will have comparable deterrent
effects on more dangerous kinds of crime and criminals. In itself the
fact that almost 90% of home burglaries occur when the premises are
unoccupied suggests that burglars generally want to avoid confronting
armed householders. This is confirmed from statements by criminals
themselves, including the responses to the National Institute of
Justice felon survey. [117] But, again, the deterrent can not be
evaluated independent of the incentive. Compare the two in relation to
robbing liquor stores versus burglarizing occupied homes: In each
case the deterrent (being shot by the victim) is the same yet the
robbers' incentive to confrontation is immensely greater. To offset the
robbers' risk of getting shot there is the incentive of a substantial
cash take. But to off-set the risk a burglar takes by not eschewing
occupied premises there is only the prospect of adding to the goods he
steals from the home the marginal amount of cash he may get from the
person of a householder he confronts. [118] This very real difference
in the incentives to confrontations in the two crimes clearly appears
in the responses to different questions in the National Institute of
Justice felon survey: 74% of the inmates agreed "One reason burglars
avoid houses when people are home is that they fear being shot during
the crime", but only 58% agreed that "A store owner who is known to
keep a gun on the premises is not going to get robbed very often."
[119]
These and other results of the felon survey do significantly
support (albeit with significant reservations) the intuition that the
phenomenon of criminals being repelled by armed victims does deter
confrontation crime. In addition to the results just noted, 56% of the
felons agreed that "A criminal is not going to mess around with a
victim he knows is armed with a gun" and 57% that "Most criminals are
more worried about meeting an armed victim than they are about running
into the police." Over 80% of the felons felt that a criminal should
always try to determine whether his victim was armed, while 39% said
they personally had aborted at least one crime because of belief that
the intended victim was armed and 8% said they had done so "many"
times. [120] "Beyond all doubt, criminals clearly worry about
confronting an armed victim" is the summary given by the National
Institute of Justice analysts. [121] As they recognize, however, to
"worry" is not the same as to be deterred from the activity which
causes the worry -although worry may deter even an violent criminal
into committing markedly less confrontation crime than he would in its
absence. And a risk that worries even hard core violent criminals whose
courage is (as we shall see) likely to be fortified by potent
combinations of alcohol and illegal drugs, may completely deter the
less violently inclined or less experienced or less reckless criminal.
Overall the results of the felon survey suggest the deterrent effect of
victim armament is a substantial reason why some felons specialize in
non-confrontation crime only and eschew the greater immediate rewards
of confrontation crime altogether.
Yet the results are both more mixed and more complex than the gun
lobby would like to admit. [122] About 40% of the felons claimed that
in planning a crime they never even considered the possibility of being
shot by a victim -- and almost one-quarter of them said they actually
found victim armament an incentive, "an exciting challenge." [123] Some
of this can be dismissed as macho posturing. Felons may be able to be
more candid in describing the fears of criminals in the abstract than
in describing their own. But it must also be considered that a subset
of the criminal population which is disproportionately significant
because murders and accidental fatalities are so heavily concentrated
among them are characterized by a signal indifference to human life,
including their own. [124] There is no necessary inconsistency between
the attitudes of this subset and indifference -or even attraction -- to
armed victims.
Moreover, another and larger subset, the "violent predators",
[125] are characterized by very high rates of substance abuse (which
is true of the most murderous subset as well). Referring to the sub-
groups they denominated respectively as handgun or shotgun predators,
the National Institue of Justice analysts described them as "criminal
opportunists ... omnibus felons" whose days out of prison are devoted
to indiscriminate criminality -- "more or less any crime they had the
opportunity to commit." [130] Just as such omnivorousness violates the
stereotype that criminals normally stick to some specialty like
robbery, burglary or forgery, so does the omnivorousness of their
substance abuse violate stereotypes of the simple heroin or cocaine or
marijuana user. Predators are likely not only to alternate these drugs
with liquor, barbituates etc., etc., but to combine them in various
fashions. With their spirits fortified with liquor, cocaine, PCP etc.,
singly or in combination, the violent predators may be relatively
indifferent to the danger of confronting an armed victim. [131] But
even if they are not, addicts' desperation to finance their drug habits
may make them willing to court that danger.
Clearly worry about being shot by an armed victim did not deter
many of the felons in this sample from a life of confrontation crime.
Such worries may deter other criminals into non-confrontation crime and
it may reduce the rate at which even violent predators engage in
confrontation crimes. But the number of violent offenses which are
nevertheless attempted prove that many criminals on many occasions can
overcome their fears of the deterrent presented both by an armed
citizenry and by the police and the prospect of punishment by the
courts.
CONCLUSION
This article began with the proposition that both pro- and anti-
gun positions on the utility of guns against crime had been arrived at
by faith in the period before the existence of credible empirical
evidence on the issues. Having examined the evidence that has become
available in the last decade it must be concluded that parts of each
faith have been sustained:
As to actual defensive handgun uses, the evidence from surveys
both of civilians and of felons is that they are much more frequent
than has previously been realized. It may tentatively be concluded that
handguns are used as or more often to prevent the commission of crimes
than by felons attempting them. This should not be understood as
suggesting that the decision to resist a felon can be made lightly or
that their handguns automatically insulate resisters from injury. The
unique defensive value of a handgun is not the only cause for
comparatively low rates of injury among gun-armed resisters; as or more
important is the wisdom not to resist in circumstances in which this is
unlikely to succeed.
As to the gun lobby's vaunted deterrent effect of gun ownership
the evidence is even more equivocal. In general (though not without
equivocation) it does support the common sense intuition that the
average criminal has no more desire to face an armed citizen than the
average citizen has to face an armed criminal. Widespread defensive gun
ownership benefits society as a whole by deterring burglars into making
efforts to avoid occupied premises; and by deterring from confrontation
offenses altogether an unknown proportion of criminals who might
otherwise be attracted by the immediate profitability of robbery into
committing at least a few of them. Even when criminals are not so
deterred, widespread gun ownership may frighten them into reducing the
overall number of such offenses they commit; and it does frighten them
into abandoning some specific offenses -- particularly in areas where
special local programs have dramatized the likelihood of victim arms
possession. Yet it must also be noted that the possibility that gun
ownership reduces the activity level of confrontation offenders is only
an unsubstantiated speculation; gun lobby propaganda has exaggerated
the deterrent effect of gun ownership by not discounting for
displacement effects that represent no net gain in overall crime
reduction.
Finally some caveats may be offered on the limited import of the
evidence I have reviewed for issues of firearms regulation: clearly
this evidence disposes of the claim that handguns are so lacking in
social utility that courts should, in effect, ban their sale to the
general public under the doctrine of liability without fault. This
evidence likewise cuts strongly against severe statutory restrictions
based on the belief that handgun ownership offers few social benefits
to offset the harms associated with it. But even if strict liability
for guns were factually supportable, it is very evident that the courts
are unwilling to accept it as a matter of law. [136] Moreover, even if
handguns offered no benefits whatever, neither does banning them --
except as part of a policy of outlawing and confiscating guns of all
kinds. [137]
What the evidence on crime reductive utility of firearms most
definitely does not do is undercut the case for controls tailored to
deny firearms of all kinds to felons, juveniles and the mentally
impaired. Indeed, Professors Kleck and Bordua, the criminologists
principally responsible for documenting that utility, remain strongly
supportive of such controls (if carefully tailored not to prevent
handgun ownership among the responsible adult population). [138]
Moreover it is still possible to argue for going beyond control to the
prohibition and confiscation of (all kinds of) firearms if it can
realistically be posited that the net gain in reducing suicide, gun
accident and certain kinds of homicide might outweigh the reductive
effect of civilian firearms ownership on crime.
References